Emil Lask

Lask, Emil

 

Born Sept. 25, 1875, in Wadowice, Kraków Województwo; died May 26, 1915, in Galicia. German philosopher. Representative of neo-Kantianism. Student of W. Windelband and H. Rickert. Professor at the University of Heidelberg (1910).

Rejecting the Kantian concept of “thing-in-itself,” Lask attempted to preserve the concept of objective ideal being as a transcendental logical structure found in consciousness but existing independently of it and attainable through intuition. Lask linked the theory of ideal being with the theory of value, which he interpreted in the spirit of E. Husserl’s phenomenology. Lask defined philosophy as theories of values, since, according to Lask, in the sphere of ideal being everything is intentional in nature and may be reduced to the concept of value.

WORKS

Die Logik der Philosophie und die Kategorienlehre. Tübingen, 1911.
Die Lehre vom Urteil. Tübingen, 1912.
Gesammelte Schriften, vols. 1–3. Tübingen, 1923–24.

REFERENCES

Herrigel, E. “E. Lasks Wertsystem.” Logos, 1923–24, vol. 12.

T. I. OIZERMAN

References in periodicals archive ?
Emil Lask y Ernst Cassirer representarian, segun esto, los exponentes mas destacados de esta encrucijada que se reproduciria, con distintas modulaciones, en los debates mas decisivos de la filosofia contemporanea.
Para Emil Lask, por el contrario, en palabras del profesor Garcia, "es necesario establecer con la mayor claridad posible el dualismo, el caracter insuperable de la estructuracion segun la forma y la materia, la irreductibilidad de ambos componentes".
Chladenius (1710-1759) and ending with Max Weber (1864-1920), Beiser examines well-known figures like Leopold von Ranke (1795-1886) and Wilhelm Dilthey (1833-1911) as weli as some obscure characters like Moritz Lazarus (1824-1903) and Emil Lask (1875-1915).
In between, he introduces us to Emil Lask, whose promising career met an early end on the eastern front during the First World War, resurrects the shining star of Heinrich Rickert, reclaims Georg Simmel and Max Weber from the sociologists, and qualifies the importance of someone like Leopold von Ranke by suggesting that "all claims to historical paternity are artificial and suspect, especially in the case of historicism, whose roots lie so deep in the eighteenth century" (253).
The Lukacs connection must be counted as significant, remembering that in 1913 Max Weber, Lukacs, and Emil Lask had pushed the value-validity question into aesthetics and eroticism.
A strong indication of this equivocation is the way Rickert virtually disappears as the book progresses, while Emil Lask receives no more than two scant references.
Emil Lask LPh Die Logik der Philosophie und die Kategorienlehre, (1911, 21923), Tubingen, J.
Space does not permit a discussion of the remaining chapters on such matters as the term Existenz in Heidegger on its way to Sein und Zeit, the importance of Emil Lask, the move from a focus on intuition to a focus on understanding: "transposing Husserl," and the final chapter on the mathematical and hermeneutical a priori.
The greater part of the course is devoted to a historical "sounding out" of the treatment of the topic from Kant to Emil Lask.
Here the major focus is Emil Lask, whose work on logic is based on Hermann Lotze's fundamental distinction between "that which is [Seiendem] and that which holds [Geltendem], the realm of beings and the realm of validities .
To many this last will seem the most striking, notably the attention paid to Emil Lask, a brilliant figure in the circle around Rickert and Weber yet almost forgotten today.