Benedetto Croce


Also found in: Dictionary, Wikipedia.
Related to Benedetto Croce: Giovanni Gentile

Croce, Benedetto

(bānādĕt`tō krô`chā), 1866–1952, Italian philosopher, historian, and critic. He lived mostly in Naples, devoting himself to studying and writing. He founded and edited (1903–44) Critica, a review of literature, history, and philosophy, which in 1944 became Quaderni della critica. Croce was made a senator in 1910 and was minister of education (1920–21). A staunch opponent of Fascism, he lived in retirement until 1943, when he became a leader of the Liberal party. Croce's system of philosophy is related to the idealistic school in that spirit, monistic in manifestation, constitutes the only reality. In his works on aesthetics Croce held that an artist's mental images, communicated by physical artifacts, constitute works of art. Viewing history as an interpretation of the past, he argued that history is not only a form of thought but the culmination of philosophy. The general title of the work presenting his system is Philosophy of the Spirit (1902–17; tr. 1909–21), which is divided into four parts, Aesthetic as Science of Expression and General Linguistic, Logic as the Science of Pure Concept, Philosophy of the Practical, and History: Its Theory and Practice. Among his other works are A History of Italy, 1871–1915 (1927; tr. 1929) and History as the Story of Liberty (1938; tr. 1941).

Bibliography

See his essays My Philosophy (tr. 1949); M. E. Moss, Benedetto Croce Reconsidered (1987); D. Roberts, Benedetto Croce and the Uses of Historicism (1987).

Croce, Benedetto

 

Born Feb. 25, 1866, in Pescasseroli, near L’Aquila; died Nov. 20, 1952, in Naples. Italian idealist philosopher, historian, literary scholar, critic, publicist, and political figure; neo-Hegelian.

From 1902 to 1920, Croce was a professor in Naples. In 1903, together with G. Gentile, he began publishing the journal La critica, which subsequently turned into a publication containing almost exclusively Croce’s own articles and reviews. (After 1944 the journal appeared irregularly under the title Quaderni della critica.) Croce was the most outstanding representative of Italian liberalism. In 1910 he became a senator; in 1920–21 he was minister of public instruction. After Mussolini came to power and throughout the German occupation of Italy, Croce was an opponent of the fascist regime. From 1943 to 1947 he headed the Liberal Party, which he refounded.

Croce’s world view was formed under the influence of the school of Neapolitan Hegelianism (B. Spaventa and F. De Sanctis). Thanks to A. Labriola, whose lectures he attended, Croce became acquainted with Marxism; however, despite his interest in Marxist philosophy and sociology (shown in his work, Historical Materialism and the Economics of Karl Marx, 1901), Croce remained an opponent of Marxism. He played a prominent role in the struggle against positivism in Italy.

Croce’s study of G. Vico greatly contributed to the formation of his own philosophy, which he defined as absolute idealism. Spirit manifests itself in theoretical (logical and aesthetic) and practical (ethical and economic) forms. While the logical and the ethical are directed toward the universal, the aesthetic and economic are directed toward the particular. Therefore, Croce’s philosophy is divided into four spheres: aesthetics, logic, the philosophy of economics, and ethics. Croce describes the relationship between the forms of spirit in terms of a dialectic of unity and distinctness of concepts, which he substitutes for the Hegelian principle of contradiction. These spiritual forms are joined into dyads; the first level, aesthetic intuition, is autonomous in relation to the second level, which is the logical concept (the moment of distinctness); but the second level presupposes the first (which is the moment of unity).

In the process of cognition, Croce laid great stress on intuition, which, in distinction to logical thought, grasps the world in its concreteness and unduplicable individuality. Intuition is embodied in an infinite variety of works of art. Therefore, the philosophy of intuition is, precisely, aesthetics, which Croce defined as “the science of expression” and identified with “general linguistics.” Croce saw the essence of poetry in “pure” or “lyrical” intuition, free from logical or moral demands; for this reason, he juxtaposed poetry, as a form of disinterested contemplation, to “prose” and “literature,” which express moral, intellectual, and similar cultural values.

Since for Croce spirit is historical in its nature, philosophy is essentially the philosophy of history, just as history, for its part, is also philosophy, since the historian recognizes the universal in the particular, always understanding the past on the basis of the present. Croce was the founder of the influential “ethical-political school” of Italian historiography and was himself one of the most important Italian historians of the 20th century and the author of numerous works on the history of culture, the arts, and social life, including the history of Italy between 1871 and 1915 and the history of Europe in the 19th century.

Croce’s aesthetic ideas received their greatest recognition outside Italy and had a significant influence on the development of literary scholarship and linguistics (including the idealist school of philology of K. Vossler and L. Spitzer). Croce had a very great influence on all branches of the humanities in Italy during the first decades of the 20th century. His influence declined in the 1940’s, thanks in particular to the works of the Italian Marxists (for example, A. Gramsci), who subjected the idealist views of Croce and his followers to criticism.

WORKS

Filosofia dello spirito, vols. 1–4. Bari, 1927–32.
Saggi filosofici, vols. 1–14. Ban, 1922–52.
Scritti di storia letteraria e politico, vols. 1–44. Bari, 1911–54.
Scritti varii, vols. 1–12. Bari, 1927–63.
Epistolario, vols. 1–2. Naples, 1967–69.
In Russian translation:
Istoricheskii materializm i marksistskaia ekonomiia. St. Petersburg, 1902.
Estetika kak nauka o vyrazhenii i kak obshchaia lingvistika, part 1. Moscow, 1920.

REFERENCES

Abbate, M. Filosofiia B. Kroche i krizis ital’ianskogo obshchestva. Moscow, 1959.
Garin, E. Khronika ital’ianskoi filosofii 20 v. Moscow, 1965. (Translated from Italian.)
Gramsci, A. O literature i iskusstve. Moscow, 1967.
Topuridze, E. M. Estetika. B. Kroche. Tbilisi, 1967.
Efirov, S. A. Ital’ianskoi burzhuaznaia filosofiia 20 v. Moscow, 1968. Chapter 2.
Gramsci, A. II materialismo storico e la filosofia di B. Croce, 2nd ed. Turin, 1949.
Cione, E. B. Croce, 2nd ed. Milan, 1953.
Cione, E. Bibliografia crociana. [Monza] 1956.
Olgiati, F. B. Croce e lo storicismo. Milan, 1953.
Agazzi, E. II giovane Croce e il marxismo. Turin, 1962.
Nicolini, F. B. Croce. Turin, 1962.
Bausola, A. Filosofia e storia net pensiero crociano. Milan, 1965.
Bausola, A. Etica e politica nel pensiero di B. Croce. Milan, 1966.
Cinquant’ anni di vita intellettuale italiana, 2nd ed., vols. 1–2. Naples, 1966.

N. V. KOTRELEV

References in periodicals archive ?
2) Benedetto Croce, Guide to Aesthetics (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 1996, trans.
After Immanuel Kant's death in 1804 the philosophical current of Idealism journeyed from Germany (with Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel) to Italy, where it found favour with Benedetto Croce and Giovanni Gentile; but with Gentile's death in 1944 and Croce's in 1952 "ended the era of Italian Philosophy" (vii) according to Brian and Rebecca Copenhaver.
In this article he reminded everyone interested that not so long ago, the same ideals and cultural actions for which the party was being accused now, were the ideals promoted and praised by Benedetto Croce himself.
3] Central for both of us is the once influential, long misunderstood, and now neglected Italian thinker Benedetto Croce (1866-1952), who ended up propounding what he called an "absolute historicism.
Subtle, though seminal, interpretive shifts as those defined by Fubini's essay seem incommensurate with such momentous historical events (one rather expects earth-shattering changes); and Fubini's essay indeed constitutes a rather ambivalent homage to Benedetto Croce while offering an unusual image of the Neapolitan philosopher as a compassionate rather than olympically aloof personality (an image that has been only recently retrieved thanks to the admirable effort of Fabio Fernando Rizi).
La Penna concludes her essay by lamenting the paucity, in Italy, of innovative studies dedicated to translation theory, which she ascribes to the "strong traditions of historical linguistics and stylistics" (21) and to the long-lasting influence of Benedetto Croce, who regarded translation as mere approximation.
of Georgia) presents a thorough look at historicism and Fascism in Italy since the early twentieth century, using the conflicting ideological views of Benedetto Croce (1866- 1952) and Giovanni Gentile (1875-1944) as a basis for a wider discussion on politics and ideas.
Epilogue to one golden age or prologue to another, Seicento Naples lacks the musical reputation of Venice and Rome, despite the best efforts of such giants of the past century as Salvatore di Giacomo, Benedetto Croce, and Ulisse Prota-Giurleo.
The author is careful to give prominence to recent Italian writing, and in an initial brief historiographical sketch the name of Benedetto Croce, the doyen of a generation ago, is mentioned, but the author has a quite negative view of Crocean historical idealism and thinks current Italian historians are mostly in revoit against it.
Such significant personages as Benedetto Croce, John Dewey, Karl Jaspers, Jacques Maritain, and Bertrand Russell were made honorary presidents.
Benedetto Croce, History as the Story of Liberty (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 2000), 26.
There has always been a stigma attached to the figure of Benedetto Croce in the form of a random but insistent accusation that Croce was a supporter of the Fascist party and Mussolini in the early years.