Bertrand Russell


Also found in: Dictionary, Thesaurus, Wikipedia.
Related to Bertrand Russell: Russell's paradox

Bertrand Russell

(person)
(1872-1970) A British mathematician, the discoverer of Russell's paradox.

Bertrand Russell

(2)
This article is provided by FOLDOC - Free Online Dictionary of Computing (foldoc.org)
The following article is from The Great Soviet Encyclopedia (1979). It might be outdated or ideologically biased.

Russell, Bertrand

 

Born May 18, 1872, in Trelleck, Wales; died Feb. 2, 1970, in Penrhyndeudraeth, Wales. English philosopher, logician, mathematician, sociologist, and public figure.

From 1910 to 1916, Russell was a professor at Cambridge University, from which he had graduated in 1894. He was also a professor at various universities in Great Britain and the United States. In 1908 he became a fellow of the Royal Society. He visited Soviet Russia in 1919.

In his philosophy, Russell underwent a complex evolution, one that he himself characterized as a transition from a Platonic interpretation of Pythagoreanism to Humism. After a shortlived enthusiasm for neo-Hegelianism in its British version, Russell turned to a Platonic variant of idealism and then, under the influence of G. Moore and A. N. Whitehead, to neorealism. Approaching neopositivism in the 1920’s and 1930’s, Russell acknowledged the sole reality of sensory data treated in the spirit of neutral monism, a concept that regarded spirit and matter as logical constructions derived from sensory data. In the 1940’s and 1950’s he turned to the ideas of D. Hume: he admitted the existence of “facts,” which, in contrast to “experience,” were objective, but whose objectivity was based on belief in the existence of the external world.

Russell’s philosophic evolution corresponded to changes in his broad plan to apply the techniques of mathematical logic to theoretical-cognitive studies. In the neorealistic and neopositivistic stages of his evolution, this plan resulted in the dissolution of the theory of knowledge in logical analysis, but subsequently Russell once again acknowledged the independent significance of philosophic problems.

Russell was the creator of the concept of logical atomism and the founder of the philosophy of logical analysis.

A good deal of what Russell wrote treats philosophic questions of mathematics. A paradox of set theory discovered by Russell—called the Russell paradox—led him to construct an original variant of the axiomatic theory of sets and to later attempt reducing mathematics to logic. In Principia Mathematica (1910–13), a three-volume work coauthored with A. N. Whitehead, Russell systematized and developed the deductive-axiomatic construction of logic in an attempt to arrive at a logical substantiation of mathematics. Russell also devised an original theory of descriptions.

In his sociological views, Russell was close to psychologism. He believed that instincts and passions underlie the historical process and human behavior. He asserted that it was impossible to distinguish the main factor among the totality of factors determining historical changes or to establish objective historical laws. In ethics and politics he held to bourgeois liberalism, opposing theories that advocated the absorption of the person by society and the state. His attitude toward Christianity, and in particular toward the hypocrisy of religious ethics, was a negative one; to religious ethics he counterposed the ethics of the science free from the unreasonable.

Characteristic features of Russell’s ethical and sociopolitical positions were an active struggle against fascism, an anti-imperialist orientation, and implacable opposition to war and violent and aggressive methods in international politics. Russell, a founder of the Pugwash movement, stood on the side of progressive social forces favoring the prohibition of nuclear weapons and working for peaceful coexistence. He won the Nobel Prize for literature in 1950.

WORKS

Scientific Method in Philosophy. Oxford, 1914.
Our Knowledge of the External World. Chicago-London, 1915.
Principles of Social Reconstruction. London, 1916.
The Problems of Philosophy. London [1920].
The Analysis of Mind. New York-London, 1924.
Religion and Science. New York, 1935.
Power: A New Social Analysis. New York [1938].
Philosophy and Politics. London, 1947.
Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy. London, 1953.
The Analysis of Matter. New York-London [1954].
Logic and Knowledge. London, 1956.
Mysticism and Logic. New York, 1957.
My Philosophical Development. New York, 1959.
Fact and Fiction. London, 1961.
An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth. London [1967].
The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell, vols. 1–3. London, 1967–69.
In Russian translation:
Germanskaia sotsial-demokratiia. St. Petersburg, 1906.
Problemy filosofii. St. Petersburg, 1914.
Mozdeistvie nauki na obshchestvo. Moscow, 1952.
Chelovecheskoe poznanie: Ego sfera i granitsy. Moscow, 1957.
Pochemu ia ne khristianin. Moscow, 1958.
Istoriia zapadnoi filosofii. Moscow, 1959.

REFERENCES

Istoriia filosofii, vol. 5. Moscow, 1961. Chapter 13.
Narskii, I. S. Filosofiia B. Rassela. Moscow, 1962.
Bykhovskii, B. E., and B. V. Meerovskii. “Ateizm Bertrana Rassela.” In Ot Erazma Rotterdamskogo do Bertrana Rassela. Moscow, 1969.
Narskii, I. S., and E. F. Pomogaeva. “Bertran Rassell—filosof i gumanist.” Moprosy filosofii, 1972, no. 6.
Bogomolov, A. S. Angliiskaia burzhuaznaia filosofiia XX veka. Moscow, 1973. Chapter 5.
The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell. Edited by P. A. Schilpp. London, 1952.
Bertrand Russell, Philosopher of the Century: Essays in his Honour. Edited by R. Schoenman. London, 1967.

I. S. NARSKII

The Great Soviet Encyclopedia, 3rd Edition (1970-1979). © 2010 The Gale Group, Inc. All rights reserved.
References in periodicals archive ?
So, Bertrand Russell's position is not so much a position due to a lack of evidence, but his lack of development of the capacity to recognize the evidence as such.
Would you rather have lunch with actress Angelina Jolie or philosopher Bertrand Russell?
What specific circumstances led Dora Black and Bertrand Russell to the civil ceremony in Battersea Town Hall on that September Tuesday in 1921?
As a fellow-pacifist, Bertrand Russell remarked: "It is preoccupation with possession, more than anything else, that prevents man from living freely and nobly."
He recalled a meeting with well-known pacifist and philosopher Bertrand Russell that sparked his political awakening.
The visit of Bertrand Russell to China during 1920 to 1921 was one of the most significant events in May Fourth Movement, and Russell pointed out that education was the most important thing for Chinese reconstruction.
Collins' sermon in St Paul's Cathedral in connection with the European gathering held two days earlier in 1958, and Bertrand Russell speaking in his Millbank flat in 1958, reading the so-called Basel Address concerning the dangers inherent in the nuclear arms race.
Wells, Bernard Shaw, Bertrand Russell. In this book he is mentor and spiritual guide through the Lenten and Easter season.
Knowing what nuclear fallout did, he was committed to peace, a mover shaker along with Bertrand Russell and a gaggle of Nobel Laureates and laureates-to-be in the extremely influential Pugwash Conferences on Science and World Affairs, named after the town in Nova Scotia they could all afford (in terms of time as well as money) to gather in at the same time.
Also in 1957 British publisher George Allen and Unwin released Bertrand Russell's Why I Am Not a Christian and Other Essays on Religion and Related Subjects.
One list pulled 7.5 percent and he got 5,300 subs almost immediately, including Bertrand Russell, Eleanor Roosevelt, and Albert Einstein.