George Berkeley


Also found in: Dictionary, Thesaurus, Wikipedia.

Berkeley, George

(bär`klē, bûr–), 1685–1753, Anglo-Irish philosopher and clergyman, b. Co. Kilkenny, Ireland. Educated at Trinity College, Dublin, he became a scholar and later a fellow there. Most of Berkeley's important work in philosophy was done in his younger years. His Essay Towards a New Theory of Vision (1709), A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (1710), and the famous Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous (1713) are among his more important works. At considerable personal sacrifice he organized a movement to establish a college in the Bermudas to convert the indigenous peoples, going to Rhode Island in 1728 to wait for promised support. This support never came, and after three years he returned to England. He was made bishop of Cloyne in 1734. Berkeley in his subjective idealism went beyond LockeLocke, John
, 1632–1704, English philosopher, founder of British empiricism. Locke summed up the Enlightenment in his belief in the middle class and its right to freedom of conscience and right to property, in his faith in science, and in his confidence in the goodness of
..... Click the link for more information.
, who had argued that such qualities as color and taste arise in the mind while primary qualities of matter such as extension and weight have existence independent of the mind. Berkeley held that both types of qualities are known only in the mind and that therefore there is no existence of matter independent of perception (esse est percipi). The observing mind of God makes possible the continued apparent existence of material objects. God arouses sensations in us in a regular coherent order. Selves and God make up the universe. Berkeley felt that his argument constituted a complete disproof of atheism. He believed that qualities, not things, are perceived and that the perception of qualities is relative to the perceiver.

Bibliography

See edition of his works by A. A. Luce and T. E. Jessop (9 vol., 1948–57); G. Pitcher, ed., The Philosophy of George Berkeley (8 vol., 1988–89); biographies by J. O. Urmson (1982) and G. J. Warnock (1983).

The Columbia Electronic Encyclopedia™ Copyright © 2013, Columbia University Press. Licensed from Columbia University Press. All rights reserved. www.cc.columbia.edu/cu/cup/
The following article is from The Great Soviet Encyclopedia (1979). It might be outdated or ideologically biased.

Berkeley, George

 

Born Mar. 12,1685, near Kilkenny, Ireland; died Jan. 14, 1753, at Oxford. English philosopher; representative of subjective idealism.

Berkeley was born into an English gentry family. He studied at Dublin University. In 1734 he became bishop of Cloyne (Ireland).

Berkeley criticized the concept of matter as the material basis (substance) of bodies, the teaching of I. Newton on space as the receptacle of all natural bodies, and the teaching of J. Locke on the origin of concepts of matter and space. According to Berkeley, it is impossible to form general ideas of space and matter by abstracting from the particular properties of individual things: we do not have sensory perception of matter as such. Contrary to Locke, Berkeley asserted that our minds can form a general idea of a thing, but not a general idea of matter. Furthermore, a general idea of matter is entirely unnecessary in science or philosophy, because it adds nothing to the properties of things beyond what is given by sensory perception. Berkeley argued against the distinction between primary and secondary qualities: all qualities are secondary to the extent that their being is entirely attributable to the ability to be perceived.

Rejecting the being of matter, Berkeley recognized only the existence of spiritual being, which he divided into “ideas” and “spirits.” Ideas, subjective qualities perceived by us, are passive and involuntary; the content of our feelings and perceptions is absolutely independent of us. On the other hand, spirits are active and can be causes.

Attempting to escape the unavoidable consequences of subjective idealism that lead to solipsism, Berkeley contended that the perceiving subject is not alone and that a thing that one subject has ceased to perceive can be perceived by other subjects. But even if all subjects disappeared, things would continue to exist as the sum of ideas in the mind of god—the subject who exists eternally and who “inserts” into the consciousness of separate subjects the content of their sensations. Here Berkeley “approaches . . . objective idealism” (V. I. Lenin, Poln. sobr. soch., 5th ed., vol. 18, p. 24). As Lenin showed in Materialism and Empirical Criticism, Berkeley’s philosophy was the prototype and one of the sources of the subjective idealist theory of bourgeois philosophy of the end of the 19th century through the beginning of the 20th century.

WORKS

The Works, vols. 1–9. London, 1948–57.
In Russian translation:
Traktat o nachalakh chelovecheskogo znaniia. St. Petersburg, 1905.
Opyt novoi teorii zreniia. Kazan, 1912.
Tri razgovora. . . . Moscow, 1937.

REFERENCES

Blonskii, P. P. Uchenie Berkli o real’nosti. Kiev, [1907].
Bogomolov, A. S. Kritika sub”ektivno-idealisticheskoi filosofii Dzh. Berkli. Moscow, 1959.
Luce, A. A. Berkeley’s Immaterialism. London, 1945.
Warnock, G. J. Berkeley. London, 1953.
Ritchie, A. D. G. Berkeley. [Manchester, 1967].

V. F. ASMUS

The Great Soviet Encyclopedia, 3rd Edition (1970-1979). © 2010 The Gale Group, Inc. All rights reserved.
References in periodicals archive ?
Philosophical Commentaries, in The Works of George Berkeley Bishop of Cloyne, vol.
George Berkeley went to Trinity College Dublin and was consecrated as Bishop of Cloyne in 1734 before moving to America where he spent most of his life - the Californian city Berkeley was named after him.
For example, one of the most important modern Berkeley scholars, Arthur Aston Luce, concludes his Life of George Berkeley in this vein: "He was clearly something of a saint" (Luce 225).
Following the likes of George Berkeley and Pete Townshend, Scott French is the latest to ask this question, but his spin is personal identification, not solipsism or rock-and-roll rhetoric.
If the eighteenth-century British philosopher Bishop George Berkeley was correct in surmising that a tree falling alone in the wilderness makes no sound, then it's fair to conclude that Bayh did not really make a speech at the 1996 Democratic convention.
a comparison of Wang Yang-ming's intuitive perception with George Berkeley's "seeing is perceiving").
George Berkeley is famous as history's most ingenious defender of philosophical idealism--the view that nothing exists other than God, finite spirits, and their ideas.
In a fascinating essay Stuart Brown describes the slightly later but related group of Oxford Idealists of Collier and Norris, stimulated by Malebranche -- and according to Brown -- exerting influence upon George Berkeley.
Hogarth's robust appeal to plain common sense harmonizes with the way the great British philosophers of his age spoke, without obscurity or jargon, to honest men and women who have no problems with how the world is unless corrupted by philosophy: "We have first raised a dust," George Berkeley wrote, "And then complain we cannot see."
In the latter Mandeville responds to Dialogue II in George Berkeley's Alciphron (1732), which Stafford includes in this collection.